Библиотека
|
ваш профиль |
Psychology and Psychotechnics
Правильная ссылка на статью:
Kryuchkov K.S.
Hermeneutics of Love: New Ground for Psychological and Social Practice
// Психология и Психотехника.
2018. № 1.
С. 48-58.
DOI: 10.7256/2454-0722.2018.1.25701 URL: https://nbpublish.com/library_read_article.php?id=25701
Hermeneutics of Love: New Ground for Psychological and Social Practice / Герменевтика любви: новый фундамент для психологической и социальной практики
DOI: 10.7256/2454-0722.2018.1.25701Дата направления статьи в редакцию: 12-03-2018Дата публикации: 21-03-2018Аннотация: В настоящей статье проводится анализ и сравнение двух, активно развиваемых в школе американской гуманистической психологии и клинической-социальной психологии, аналитических подходов: "герменевтики любви" и "герменевтики подозрения". Автор рассматривает герменевтику не только как узкую практику интерпретации текстов, но как основу для мышления и профессионального мировоззрения, в том числе для психологической работы. "Герменевтика подозрения" является основой для многих исследовательских и терапевтических практик. В то же время, "герменевтика любви" является основанием для психологических практик, развивающихся в русле гуманистической психотерапии, в частности клиент-центрированной психотерапии К. Роджерса и ее ветвлений. Данная статья является полностью теоретической работой. Основными методами являются: анализ литературы, теоретический анализ, метод сопоставления, собственно герменевтический метод. Автор указывает, что "герменевтика любви" может являться не только подходом к интерпретации и пониманию текста, но этическим и эпистемологическим основанием для социальных практик, причем не только для психологической практики, но в целом для практик, связанных со взаимодействием с людьми, коммуникативных практик. "Герменевтика любви" предопределяет онтологическую позицию, которую занимает исследователь или практик по отношению к субъекту, тем самым она является подлинным фундаментом практики, поскольку именно на онтологии выстраивается праксис взаимодействия. Ключевые слова: Герменевтика, Герменевтика любви, Герменевтика подозрения, Основа для практики, Этика, Онтология, Эпистемология, Основа для понимания, Основа практики, Искусство интерпретацииAbstract: In the present paper, the authors will scrutinize the ‘hermeneutics of love’, the concept, which is being developed by the representatives of humanistic psychology (Selig, Robbins) as well as clinical-community psychology (McInerney). The authors deductively consider this approach from different points: ontological, axiological and gnoseological. The authors try to compare and contrast ‘hermeneutics of love’ to ‘hermeneutics of suspicion’. In addition, the authors analyze a more traditional approach to understanding. The authors consider their role as a basis for social and psychological practice and discuss different practices that are being developed under the framework of hermenutics of suspicion and, on the other hand, the hermenutics of love. The authors also introuce hermenutics of love as a basis of psychology in ‘human science’ in contrast to that in ‘natural science’. Keywords: Hermeneutics, Hermeneutics of love, Hermeneutics of suspicion, Ground for practice, Ethics, Onthology, Epistemology, Grounds for understanding, Basis for practice, Art of interpretationHermeneutics as a philosophical approach: the roots Originally, the word ‘hermeneutics’ is the latin form of the greek word ‘hermeneutice’ which refers to the specific type of knowledge in contrast to ‘sofia’ – the knowledge of what has been said or revealed and which does not deal with the truth-value of what the content (Ramberg, Gjesdal, 2014). Antic authors such as Plato and Aristotle referred to this term as to the practice of scrutinizing and refutation of the text, not as the practice of understanding texts per se. It was not until the Stoicism that Hermeneutics started to be understood as the methodology of the textual understanding (ibid). Augustine invested a lot into the textual studies. For instance, in his work De Doctrina Christiana he distinguishes things and signs. According to Woo (2013): ‘Because the aim of his book is to understand the teaching of the Bible, Augustine divided knowledge into two: that of things (res) and that of signs (signa). Things which are not employed to signify something are learned through signs, which are employed to signify something’ […] ‘God can communicate with the believer through the signs of the Scriptures. Thus, humiliation, love, and the knowledge of signs are an essential hermeneutical presupposition for a sound interpretation of the Scriptures’ (ibid.). So there we may see an appearance of the specific presuppositions necessary for understanding. Augustine also regards the duplex commandment of love in Matthew 22 as the heart of Christian faith (ibid.), so, love may also be named as one of presuppositions. Not only works of Augustine, but also by such prominent authors such as Martin Luther, Giambattista Vico, Benedict Spinoza and some others, influenced modern hermeneutics (Ramberg, Gjesdal, 2014). The first more or less accurate theory of interpretation, which sets a number of normative rules for the interpretative process, has been offered by Johann Martin Chladenius (ibid). Chladenius distinguished hermeneutics from logic and offered a classification of points of view. Accordingly, he explains how variations in our perception may interfere with our understanding of texts (ibid). German Philosopher Friedrich Ast offered another system. According to Ramberg and Gjesdal (2014): ‘Individual utterances are neither to be understood with reference to their author, nor with reference to their place within the semiotic system, but according to their location within world-history. This, Ast thought, was possible through the combination of a synthetic and an analytic approach, the former focusing on the whole, the latter on the particular parts of which this whole consists. Ast thereby extends the scope of the hermeneutic circle’. Another important name is August Wolf, who is often considered as one of the predecessors of the so called ‘romantic hermeneutics’. Wolf claimed, that in addition to concentrate on the knowledge of the object studies should also concentrate on the relevance of the object and the method through which it was obtained. For instance: studying antic texts, one should be aware not only about the general culture, but also about the individuality of an author (ibid.). ‘Romantic Hermeneutics’: what we usually call hermeneutics So called ‘romantic hermeneutics’ is what the hermeneutics in general referred to by the most. Friedrich Schleiermacher, who may be called ‘a father’ of romantic (modern) hermeneutics, extended the scope of the art and a science of textual understanding and interpretation from the sacred texts to all kind of texts and to the human communication in general (Forster, 2013). He concluded, that the good understanding of text must be prepared by the understanding of the context where this text was born. Schleiermacher also claimed that each interpretation has two sides: linguistic and psychological. Linguistic interpretation is mainly concerned with what is common or shared in a language; psychological interpretation mainly with what is distinctive to a particular author (ibid.). Important extension of Schleiermacher concept has been given by W. Dilthey. According to Dilthey, scientific explanation of nature must be completed with a theory of how the world is given to us through symbolically mediated practices (Ramber, Gjesdal, 2014). Dilthey distinguished the lived experience from an understanding (Erlebnis and Verstahen). Experience does not automatically lead to the self-understanding, self-understanding is obtained only to the extent that the self relates to itself as it relates to others, i.e., in a mediated way (ibid.). Martin Heidegger being under the influence of Husserl’s and Brentano ideas of intentionality, shifted the focus of hermeneutics from interpretation to an existential understanding. He tried to apply that to actual psychiatric and psychotherapeutic practice which then gave a rise to Medard Boss’s Dasein Analysis (see, Heidegger, ‘Being and Time’ and ‘Zollikon Seminars’). One of the most influential philosophers of the XX century, Hans-Georg Gadamer was the key-figure in the development of hermeneutics. Being under the influence of Heidegger, Gadamer asserted that methodical contemplation is opposite to experience and reflection. We can reach the truth only by understanding or mastering our experience. According to Gadamer, our understanding is not fixed but rather is changing and always indicating new perspectives. The most important thing is to unfold the nature of individual understanding. One of the most important claims made by Gadamer is that our being is based on so called ‘prejudices’ or ‘pre-judgements’ which are, according to Gadamer and contrary to Husserlian phenomenology) the positive things. Each text is created within the context which constitutes prejudices. In addition to that, text is not only being created in within the context but also is being understood within that. Which means – to understand the text one must understand one’s own prejudices in addition, understand the context where the text has been written - thus understand the author and thus, finally, obtain an understanding of the text (Gadamer, 1975). Another author which had a great impact on hermeneutics was Jurgen Habermas, representative of so-called critical hermeneutics. Habermas criticized Gadamer’s approach for too much laying on tradition and historical context. According to Habermas, much more important is not just an analysis of the way in which we de facto are conditioned by history but a set of quasi-transcendental principles of validity in terms of which the claims of the tradition may be subjected to evaluation. In other words, Habermas emphasized the role of critical reflection in the process of interpretation. (Ramberg, Gjesdal, 2014). Habermas endowed a lot into the theory of communication and socio-political science. Paul Ricouer agrees to Habermas and his followers about the role of critical thinking in the process of interpretation. However, he does not agree with the statement, that in order to achieve that, the historical tradition must be put aside. Ricouer emphasizes how the text itself may open up a space of existential and political possibilities (ibid.). Concluding the paragraph considering the historical development of hermeneutics we should mention the very important term – ‘hermeneutic circle’ which has been described by Schleiermacher as the movement from the individual parts of text to the whole text back and forth. We will not go deeper into the descriptions of different positions regarding the hermeneutic circle, but just leave a note that different thinkers had different attitudes to this term. Hermeneutics has a lot of applications in the different areas of science and social practices. For example, psychology (see works by S. Kvale and our further paragraphs) or legal studies (see works of E. Betti). Hermeneutics as a ground for research and applied psychology As we said above, hermeneutics is a ground both for research and an applied psychology. Below we will consider the role, hermeneutics plays in both of these areas. Hermeneutics as a ground for research psychology. The most obvious direction in research psychology which roots are traceable to hermeneutics is qualitative psychology or in other words, qualitative research methodology in psychology. According to Packer, Addison (1989), Davidsen (2012), Smith (2004, 2009, 2015), Creswell (2009), Laverty (2003), Kafle (2011), Kvale (2009), also, Bousygina (2013), and Vorobyeva (2013), hermeneutics is a basis for qualitative researches and interpretative studies. Creswell (2009) noted, that hermeneutic researches in psychology are oriented toward lived experience and interpreting the texts of life researchers first turn to a phenomenon which interests them, reflect on essential themes, then write a description of the phenomenon maintaining a strong relation to the topic of inquiry and balancing the parts of writing to the whole. It is an interpretive process in which the researcher makes an interpretation of the meaning of the lived experiences. In other words, hermeneutics is a basis for an interpretation widely used in qualitative analysis. Laverty (2003), Vorobyeva (2013) and Kafle (2011) emphasize the term ‘hermeneutic phenomenology’, distinguishing it from ‘pure’ phenomenology as based not on perception (‘pure’ and unbiased) but on pre-understanding of the world which is not something a person can step outside of or put aside, as it is understood as already being with us in the world. While still being phenomenological in a sense of ‘gathering’ the ‘data’, It is an attempt to unveil the world as experienced by the subject through their life world stories, or in other words, a turn from description to interpretation (Boussygina, 2009a). On a more technical level, hermeneutics is a basis for the very specific research techniques, such as interpretative analysis (see. Smith, 2015; Bousygina, 2009b). Bousygina (2009b) describes traditional and ‘deep’ variations of hermeneutics analysis in psychology. Hermeneutics offers very specific techniques and modes to interpret the concrete data such as ‘meaning categorization’ (in contrast to phenomenological ‘meaning condensation’) (see, for example, Kvale, 2009; Bousygina, 2009b; Smith, 2009, 2015)). So hermeneutics is an important part of research psychology not only as something that underlies qualitative research philosophy, but also as a source and root for the very specific research techniques. Hermeneutics as a basis for applied psychology. There is a large amount of literature dedicated to an important role of hermeneutics for applied psychology and psychotherapy. As we mentioned above, the whole school of Dasein-analysis, founded by M. Boss, was grounded on hermeneutics developed by Martin Heidegger (see, Boss (ed.), 2001; Wilberg, 2003). Vorobyeva (2013) offers E. Gendlin’s focusing as an example of an approach based on phenomenological hermeneutics. The very Freudian psychoanalysis has an art of an interpretation as its heart and soul, so it is implicitly based on hermeneutics (see, for example, Bousygina, 2012, 2013; Steele, 1979; Ricoeur, 2008; Terwee, 2012), as well as the humanistic psychology undoubtly has traceable hermeneutics roots (Rennie, 2007). So there is no doubts that hermeneutics is an important ‘way of thought’ or ‘philosophical direction’ that underlies both different research and practical schools and methods in psychology. Hermeneutics of suspicion: what is ‘the usual’ interpretation in psychology As was stated by Ricoeur (1970/2008) and was then widely acknowledged both in philosophy (see, Gadamer, 1984) and in psychology (see: Hay, 1999, Josselson, 2004; Langdridge, 2008) hermeneutics of suspicion is a practice of interpretation which is aimed to decode meanings that are disguised. Gadamer (1984) noted that these radical suspicion was introduced by Nietzsche. Psychoanalysis is fully grounded onto this kind of interpretation, it is the basic presupposition of it that one never actually means what one says (see, Langdridge, 2008; Leiter, 2006; Clarke, 2006; Dean, 2002; Blatt et. al, 2006; Strowick, 2005). So, in psychoanalytical setting, as Langdrige quite accurately noted, researcher's (therapist’s) care of the subject becomes secondary to attempts to engage in crudely reductionist explanatory analyses. The very same might be said with regard to the cognitive-behavioral therapy where one’s actions are attached with one’s mindsets, cognitive distortions, conditioning, virtually anything but one’s free will (see, for example: Kuss, Griffiths, 2015; Elliott et. al, 2011; Gordon, 2009). Taking into account that psychodynamic approaches grown out of psychoanalysis and the CBT are obviously among the most usable therapy approaches in the world, we believe, it is legitimate to say that the ‘usual’ kind of interpretation we get in psychological practice is that of suspicion. It puts aside human dignity making person nothing more than an object affected by an external stimuli (where ‘unconscious’ can legitimately be set as an ‘external’ with regard to person’s will). Ontologically, hermeneutics of suspicion does not regard a person as an agent of own being and actions. Person is an object affected by different external impacts. Logically it is derived that ethically such person does not have human dignity, his/her life and will do not belong to him/her. Epistemologically once more, it means that a person is a weak-willed subject/object on which any kind of manipulations may be performed, regardless of his/her own will and well-being. That is why it is important to seek an alternative mode of interpretation, which is, to us, hermeneutics of love which is discussed below. Hermeneutics of love: foundations From the first glimpse the term ‘hermeneutics of love’ may seem paradoxal – ‘interpretation of love’. This concept is somewhat well-developed in religious and literature studies where it is used as an interpretative tool and an alternative to the hermeneutics of suspicion (see: Shafer, 1994; Netland, 2007; Jeanrond, 2010; Winston, 2018). It is not yet broadly developed in psychology, though in some areas, such as in humanistic clinical-community psychology (an area that applies clinical and psychotherapeutic approach to the issues of the whole community) this approach is being used. Even though this concept have implicitly existed in the humanistic and existential approaches in psychology (as it will be demonstrated below), an explication of this concept will make it possible to provide professionals with the general ground, the framework, that will create the unite ‘language’ for ‘so different, but not such distant’ approaches within the large variety of ‘third force’ (existential, humanistic, person-centered) approaches. Based on papers by authors representing hermeneutics of love, such as Robins (2015), McInerney (2015), and Selig (2015) and some others (see for example, Crisp, 2017; Cristopher, Campbell, 2008; Wiliams, Gantt, 2013 etc.) we can give this approach a name – ‘hermeneutics on love’, as hermeneutics based on love. In a short, love as agape love seems to be the main prejudice for such hermeneutics. Scrutinizing the hermeneutics of love first of all it should be noticed that here ‘hermeneutics’ is understood mainly not as a narrow interpretative practice, but broader as an epistemological position for both social science and practice. Selig (2015) defines the hermeneutics of love as ‘the act of interpreting with love, through love, and for love, including the intention to take action on behalf of love’. McInerney (2015) shows that community practice may be based on the principles of communitas (mostly, ‘spontaneous communitas’, described by V. Turner and distinguished by him from normative and ideological communitas), munificence and allopathy grounded into the shared burdens such as alterity and finitude. It is possible to derive a definition of hermeneutics of love as broad social interpretative practice which gives basis for understanding and action in an extensive way, not limited to the textual interpretation. In other words, hermeneutics of love is the fundamental position, presupposition, on which any community action could be based. Trying to analyze the concepts, underlying hermeneutics of love, we should first define the ‘love’ which is mentioned. This is the type of love, called ‘agape’ which is different from other types such as eros or philia. According to the philosophical encyclopedia ‘‘Agape’ has come, primarily through the Christian tradition, to mean the sort of love God has for us persons, as well as our love for God and, by extension, of our love for each other—a kind of brotherly love. In the paradigm case of God's love for us, agape is “spontaneous and unmotivated,” revealing not that we merit that love but that God's nature is love (Nygren 1953, p. 85). Rather than responding to antecedent value in its object, agape instead is supposed to create value in its object and therefore to initiate our fellowship with God (pp. 87–88). Consequently, Badhwar (2003, p. 58) characterizes agape as “independent of the loved individual's fundamental characteristics as the particular person she is”; and Soble (1990, p. 5) infers that agape, in contrast to eros, is therefore not reason dependent but is rationally “incomprehensible,” admitting at best of causal or historical explanations’ (Helm, 2013). So, in a short, agape may be defined as a loving attitude without an attitude to make other belong to one. Robbins (2015) refers to Post claims: ’Agape love, a willing of the good of the other, is an interpretive stance by which the dignity of the other can be disclosed and understood’. That is obvious, that standing on this point of view, we could no more relate to other person as to a manipulable object. So, ontologically, hermeneutics of love regards an other person as a wholly other with his or her free will. One must acknowledge the freedom of the other (‘radical otherness of the other, according to McInerney). Ethically that means that we may not not to acknowledge the dignity of other person. According to Robbins (2015): ‘To say that human beings have dignity is to say that any given person is beyond price, of nonquantifiable value that is nonfungible and therefore of infinite worth (i.e., infinite in the sense that something that is priceless is infinite in worth; its value cannot be estimated and therefore no price is high enough). Therefore, ironically and paradoxically, any given person is a finite being with infinite worth. What makes the person priceless is his or her vulnerability, perishability, and mortality—in other words, his or her finitude [which is one of the shared burdens among us which provides the foundation, however, shaken and unstable, for community practices – K.K]’. So, what is the epistemological, practical position of hermeneutics of love? Robbins (2015) uses Paul’s Ricouer term ‘hermeneutics of suspicion’ to define this. Under the hermeneutics of suspicion Ricouer mention approaches (Such as Marxist or Freudian, we could add here Lacan) which imply, that what is pronounced is not what the truly meaning is. So, the other person is always ‘under the suspicion’. While hermeneutics of love ‘interprets not through a mood of fear but through the attitudes of charity, empathy, and openness. When a person is approached through these attitudes, with sincerity, it allows the person or text to reveal otherwise hidden truths, which can be communicated through a well-earned sense of trust and nondefensiveness’ (Robbins, 2015). This is very close to so-called ‘taoistic’ perspective of science, offered by A. Maslow (1993), a ‘loving perception’, which gives objectively higher accuracy in scientific work. Moving further and contrasting the hermeneutics of love with an approach commonly used by neuroscience or psychology ‘as a natural science’ it is impossible to disagree with the Maslow’s statement, that there is no value-free love. What are this values? Apart from the positivistic values of objectivity, validity, falsifiability, in the very attitude to its subjects that type of science has a value of ‘greater knowledge’. In other words, that kind of scientist presumes, that he or she knows his or her subject better than the subject oneself. Which is very equal to the hermeneutics of suspicion. The very fact how, quite often, the research objectives are being formulated, in the form of hypothesis which implies the (if we apply here the language of the theory of activity and motion) ‘projected image of the result’ (Bernstein, 1967). This result is already ‘gotten’ by the researcher – the only thing he or she needs is to confirm it – so the subject in that case is reduced to only two variables: ‘confirmation’ and ‘refutation’. Can we speak of ‘accuracy’ in that case? Yes, if we are interested in the isolated aspects of psychic or behavior (in some cases it is necessary, for example if, for example, the activity of certain group of neurons is being studied), however, in most cases, the more human aspects are studied the les accurate such approach is (even in physiological studies, when, for example, the question of ‘choice’ is about to be educed to the neuronal reaction, see, for example Behrens et. Al. (2007) ). Practice: not hermeneutics but love Given examples of hermeneutics of love provides us more of examples of applied love than hermeneutics as the study of interpretation. Unfortunately, such examples, especially, described in exact terms of hermeneutics of love, are rare. Selig (2015), for example, offers M. Luther King as an example of non-violent social and political practice. Responding non-violently to the worse acts of violence committed against him, such as bombing his house, he was continuing infallibly love his enemies. Thus, empowering his followers. According to Luther King, hatred does not empower. As it had been summarized by Selig (2015): ‘Summarized simply, violence could never bring about the beloved community’. McInerney (2015) and Goss (2015) offer hermeneutics of love as a framework for participatory-action research (PAR). They provide examples of such usage within the PAR in educational setting (McInerney, 2015) as well as within queer-theory based community PAR (Goss, McInerney, 2015). Another approach where hermeneutics of love is being developed is the Person-centered approach. Crisp (2017) offers an example of social-ethical action taken by a medical staff at a large public hospital in Australia aimed at helping an asylum seekers in Australia. Clinical, social and political action was taken in order to better conditions of those asylum-seekers needed help. Crisp offers this as an example of a constructive practice of social ethics, which, in other words, may be described as based on an applied hermeneutics of love. Another example of the practical application of the hermeneutic of love within the person-centered approach is given by Robert (Bob) Lee. This prominent follower of Carl Rogers developed the concept of conditional and unconditional mind. He derived it from his almost 50 years of psychotherapy practice. In a short this concept may be condensed in a phrase (see, picture): 'Unconditional experiencing basically involves simply being with another or others, immediate, direct, instantaneous, right here-and-now, impersonal and impartial viewing and expression takes place. In such a state of Mind, unconditional acceptance and appreciation is naturally-spontaneously happening which directly leads to clear understanding” (Lee, 2012). Conclusion Hermeneutics of love may be defined as an approach to human science and practice which is not reduced to the art of text interpretation, but to the art and science of an understanding and communication with people regardless of the area of application. Even though the concept of hermeneutics of love this was somewhat implicitly presented in the humanistic and existential approaches in psychology (such as R. May’s, V. Frankl’s and C. Rogers’), an explication of this concept is more than important as it will provide professionals with the general ground, the framework, that will create the unite ‘language’ for ‘so different, but not such distant’ approaches within the large variety of humanistic approaches (including existential, person-centered, transpersonal, etc), without limitation neither to specific school, nor to the specific area of application. Hermeneutic of love is based on the ontological view of another person as a person with own freedom and free will, which means ethically: acknowledgment of the freedom and dignity of the other and epistemologically: approaching the subjects and the valuable individuals with through the attitudes of charity, empathy openness and good will for other. This gives a ground for social and community practices in different spheres such as psychotherapy or politics, while this ground is not formalized and fixed, while being existential and liminal ‘always in motion’. We provided several examples of how this approach works from political actions to clinical and from clinical to research. This approach, being relatively new for psychology has good potential for the development in the modern psychology as the requests for social and community actions for psychologist made by society are growing gradually. Hermeneutics of love gives an opportunity to build common language and provide common grounds for 'related but distant' schools and areas of application such as different schools in psychotherapy, community psychology, researches, community actions and social work.
Библиография
1. Creswell J. (2009). Research Design: Qualitative, Quantitative, and Mixed Methods Approaches. SAGE publications.
2. Crisp R. (2017). The person-centered approach and social ethics: a cautionary tale concerning persons seeking asylum in Australia. Person-Centered & Experiential Psychotherapies, 16:3, 270-285, DOI: 10.1080/14779757.2017.1323667 3. Clarke S. (2006). Theory and Practice: Psychoanalytic Sociology as Psycho-Social Studies. Sociology, vol. 40, issue 6. 4. Bousygina N.P. (2012). Psychoanalytic interpretation as research methodology. Counseling Psychology and Psychotherapy, vol. 4, pp. 60-84. 5. Bousygina N.P. (2013). Qualitative methodology in psychology: historical phases and the current state. Journal for Practicing Psychologist – Russia, vol. 4, pp. 10-31. 6. Boss M. (ed.) (2001). Zollikon Seminars. Protocols-Conversations-Letters. R. Askay & F. Mayr (trs.). Northwestern University Press: Evanston, Illinois. 7. Bousygina N.P. (2009a). The phenomenological description and interpretation: examples of the analysis of the data in qualitative psychological researches. Moscow Psychotherapy Journal, Vol. 2, pp. 52-76. 8. Behrens et. Al. (2007). Learning the value of information in an uncertain world. Nature Neuroscience, 10, 1214 – 1221. 9. Bousygina N.P. (2009b.) Phenomenological and Hermeneutic Approaches in Qualitative Psychological Research. Cultural-Historical Psychology, Vol. 1. Pp. 57-65. 10. Bernstein, N.A. (1967). The co-ordination and regulation of movements. Oxford : Pergamon Press. 11. Blatt S. et. al. (2006). Minding the Gap Between Positivism and Hermeneutics in Psychoanalytic Research. Journal of the American Psychoanalytic Association, Vol. 54, Issue, 2. 12. Badhwar N.K. (2003). Love, in H. LaFollette (ed.), Practical Ethics, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 42–69. 13. Davidsen A.S. (2012). Phenomenological Approaches in Psychology and Health Sciences, Qualitative Research in Psychology, 10:3, 318-339, DOI: 10.1080/14780887.2011.608466. 14. Dean T. (2002). Art as Symptom: Žižek and the Ethics of Psychoanalytic Criticism. Diacritics, Vol. 32, #2. 15. Elliott R. et. al. (2011). Empathy. Psychotherapy, Vol 48(1), 43-49. 16. Forster, M. (2015) "Friedrich Daniel Ernst Schleiermacher", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2015 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2015/entries/schleiermacher/ 17. Gadamer H-G. (1975). Truth and method. Seabury Press. 18. Gadamer H-G. (1984). The hermeneutics of suspicion. Man and the world, vol. 17, issues 3-4. 19. Gordon R.M. (2009). Reactions To The Psychodynamic Diagnostic Manual (PDM) By Psychodynamic, CBT And Other Non-Psychodynamic Psychologists. Issues in Psychoanalytic Psychology, Vol. 31, #1. 20. Goss R., McInerney R. (2015). Becoming “Threshold Researchers” in the Community. Toward a Queering Practice as a Hermeneutic of Lov,. Journal of Humanistic Psychology, vol. 53, issue 6, pp. 286-308. 21. Hay D. (1999). Psychologists interpreting conversion: two American forerunners of the hermeneutics of suspicion. History of the Human Sciences, vol. 12, issue 1, pp. 55-72. 22. Helm, B. "Love", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2013 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = . 23. Jeanrond, W. (2010). Toward an interreligious hermeneutics of love. In: Cornille, C. and Conway, C. (eds.) Interreligious Hermeneutics. Series: Interreligious Dialogue Series (2). Cascade Books, pp. 44-60. 24. Josselson R. (2004). The hermeneutics of faith and the hermeneutics of suspicion. Narrative Inquiry, Volume 14, Issue 1, pp. 1-24. 25. Kafle N.P. (2011). Hermeneutic phenomenological research method simplified. Bodhi: an Interdisciplinary Journal, vol. 5, pp. 181-200. 26. Kuss D.J., Griffiths M.D. (2015) Internet Addiction Treatment: The Therapists’ View. In: Internet Addiction in Psychotherapy. Palgrave Studies in Cyberpsychology. Palgrave Pivot, London. 27. Kvale S., Brinkman S. (2009). InterViews: Learning the Craft of Qualitative Research Interviewing. SAGE. 28. Landridge D. (2008). Phenomenology and Critical Social Psychology: Directions and Debates in Theory and Research. Social and Personality Psychology Compass, vol. 2, issue 3. 29. Laverty S.M. (2003). Hermeneutic Phenomenology and Phenomenology: A Comparison of Historical and Methodological Considerations. International Journal of Qualitative Methods, vol. 2, issue 3, pp. 21-35. 30. Lee, R. (2012). Conditional and unconditional experiencing in relationships. Journal of Practicing Psychologist (Zhurnal Prakticheskogo Psikhologa), 4. 31. Leiter B. (2006). The future for philosophy. Clarendon press. 32. McInerney, R.G. (2015). A hermeneutics of love for community-based, participatory action research. Journal of Humanistic Psychology, vol. 53, issue 6, pp. 263-285. 33. Netland J. (2007). Who is My Neighbor?” Reading World Literature through the Hermeneutics of Love. International Journal of Christianity & Education, Volume: 11 issue: 2, pp. 67-82. 34. Nygren, A. (1953). Agape and Eros, Philadelphia, PA: Westminster Press. 35. Packer M.J., Addison R.B. (1989). Entering the Circle: Hermeneutic Investigation in Psychology. SUNY press. 36. Ramberg, B., Gjesdal, K. (2014) "Hermeneutics", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2014 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2014/entries/hermeneutics/ 37. Rennie D. (2007). Methodical hermeneutics and humanistic psychology. The Humanistic Psychologist, Vol 35(1), 1-14. 38. Ricoeur P. (1970/2008). Freud and Philosophy: An Essay on Interpretation. Motilal Banarsidass Publishe. 39. Robbins, B.D. (2015). The heart of humanistic psychology: Human dignity disclosed through a hermeneutics of love. Journal of Humanistic Psychology, vol. 53, issue 6, pp. 223-237. 40. Selig, J.L. (2015). Borne forward ceaselessly into love: A theory of the hermeneutics of love exemplified by Martin Luther King, Jr. Journal of Humanistic Psychology, vol. 53, issue 6, pp.238-262. 41. Shafer I. (1994). From the senses to sense: the hermeneutics of love. Zygon: Journal of Religion and Science, Volume 29, issue 4. 42. Smith J. A. (2004). Reflecting on the development of interpretative phenomenological analysis and its contribution to qualitative research in psychology. Qualitative Research in Psychology, Vol. 1, issue 1. 43. Smith J.A., Flowers P., Larkin M. (2009). Interpretative Phenomenological Analysis: Theory, Method and Research. SAGE. 44. Smith J.A. (2015). Qualitative Psychology: A Practical Guide to Research Methods. SAGE. 45. Soble A. (1990). 1990, The Structure of Love, New Haven: Yale University Press 46. Steele, R. S. (1979). Psychoanalysis and hermeneutics. International Review of Psycho-Analysis, 6(4), 389-411. 47. Strowick, E. (2005). Comparative Epistemology of Suspicion: Psychoanalysis, Literature, and the Human Sciences. Science in Context, 18(4), 649-669. doi:10.1017/S0269889705000700 48. Tervee S.J.S. (2012). Hermeneutics in Psychology and Psychoanalysis. Springer science and business media. 49. Vorobyeva L.I. (2013). How hermeneutics phenomenology can be useful for psychotherapy. Journal for Practicing Psychologist – Russia, vol. 4, pp. 31-55. 50. Wilberg P. (2003). Heidegger, Medicine And 'Scientific Method': The Unheeded Message Of The Zollikon Seminars. New Gnosis Publications. 51. Williams R., Gantt E. (2013). Psychology and the death of aspiration. Theory and Psychology, Volume: 23 issue: 2. 52. Winston B. (2018). The Virtues from the Beatitudes. In: Biblical Principles of Hiring and Developing Employees. Christian Faith Perspectives in Leadership and Business. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. 53. Woo, B. Hoon (2013). "Augustine’s Hermeneutics and Homiletics in De doctrina christianae". Journal of Christian Philosophy 17: 97–117. References
1. Creswell J. (2009). Research Design: Qualitative, Quantitative, and Mixed Methods Approaches. SAGE publications.
2. Crisp R. (2017). The person-centered approach and social ethics: a cautionary tale concerning persons seeking asylum in Australia. Person-Centered & Experiential Psychotherapies, 16:3, 270-285, DOI: 10.1080/14779757.2017.1323667 3. Clarke S. (2006). Theory and Practice: Psychoanalytic Sociology as Psycho-Social Studies. Sociology, vol. 40, issue 6. 4. Bousygina N.P. (2012). Psychoanalytic interpretation as research methodology. Counseling Psychology and Psychotherapy, vol. 4, pp. 60-84. 5. Bousygina N.P. (2013). Qualitative methodology in psychology: historical phases and the current state. Journal for Practicing Psychologist – Russia, vol. 4, pp. 10-31. 6. Boss M. (ed.) (2001). Zollikon Seminars. Protocols-Conversations-Letters. R. Askay & F. Mayr (trs.). Northwestern University Press: Evanston, Illinois. 7. Bousygina N.P. (2009a). The phenomenological description and interpretation: examples of the analysis of the data in qualitative psychological researches. Moscow Psychotherapy Journal, Vol. 2, pp. 52-76. 8. Behrens et. Al. (2007). Learning the value of information in an uncertain world. Nature Neuroscience, 10, 1214 – 1221. 9. Bousygina N.P. (2009b.) Phenomenological and Hermeneutic Approaches in Qualitative Psychological Research. Cultural-Historical Psychology, Vol. 1. Pp. 57-65. 10. Bernstein, N.A. (1967). The co-ordination and regulation of movements. Oxford : Pergamon Press. 11. Blatt S. et. al. (2006). Minding the Gap Between Positivism and Hermeneutics in Psychoanalytic Research. Journal of the American Psychoanalytic Association, Vol. 54, Issue, 2. 12. Badhwar N.K. (2003). Love, in H. LaFollette (ed.), Practical Ethics, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 42–69. 13. Davidsen A.S. (2012). Phenomenological Approaches in Psychology and Health Sciences, Qualitative Research in Psychology, 10:3, 318-339, DOI: 10.1080/14780887.2011.608466. 14. Dean T. (2002). Art as Symptom: Žižek and the Ethics of Psychoanalytic Criticism. Diacritics, Vol. 32, #2. 15. Elliott R. et. al. (2011). Empathy. Psychotherapy, Vol 48(1), 43-49. 16. Forster, M. (2015) "Friedrich Daniel Ernst Schleiermacher", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2015 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2015/entries/schleiermacher/ 17. Gadamer H-G. (1975). Truth and method. Seabury Press. 18. Gadamer H-G. (1984). The hermeneutics of suspicion. Man and the world, vol. 17, issues 3-4. 19. Gordon R.M. (2009). Reactions To The Psychodynamic Diagnostic Manual (PDM) By Psychodynamic, CBT And Other Non-Psychodynamic Psychologists. Issues in Psychoanalytic Psychology, Vol. 31, #1. 20. Goss R., McInerney R. (2015). Becoming “Threshold Researchers” in the Community. Toward a Queering Practice as a Hermeneutic of Lov,. Journal of Humanistic Psychology, vol. 53, issue 6, pp. 286-308. 21. Hay D. (1999). Psychologists interpreting conversion: two American forerunners of the hermeneutics of suspicion. History of the Human Sciences, vol. 12, issue 1, pp. 55-72. 22. Helm, B. "Love", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2013 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = . 23. Jeanrond, W. (2010). Toward an interreligious hermeneutics of love. In: Cornille, C. and Conway, C. (eds.) Interreligious Hermeneutics. Series: Interreligious Dialogue Series (2). Cascade Books, pp. 44-60. 24. Josselson R. (2004). The hermeneutics of faith and the hermeneutics of suspicion. Narrative Inquiry, Volume 14, Issue 1, pp. 1-24. 25. Kafle N.P. (2011). Hermeneutic phenomenological research method simplified. Bodhi: an Interdisciplinary Journal, vol. 5, pp. 181-200. 26. Kuss D.J., Griffiths M.D. (2015) Internet Addiction Treatment: The Therapists’ View. In: Internet Addiction in Psychotherapy. Palgrave Studies in Cyberpsychology. Palgrave Pivot, London. 27. Kvale S., Brinkman S. (2009). InterViews: Learning the Craft of Qualitative Research Interviewing. SAGE. 28. Landridge D. (2008). Phenomenology and Critical Social Psychology: Directions and Debates in Theory and Research. Social and Personality Psychology Compass, vol. 2, issue 3. 29. Laverty S.M. (2003). Hermeneutic Phenomenology and Phenomenology: A Comparison of Historical and Methodological Considerations. International Journal of Qualitative Methods, vol. 2, issue 3, pp. 21-35. 30. Lee, R. (2012). Conditional and unconditional experiencing in relationships. Journal of Practicing Psychologist (Zhurnal Prakticheskogo Psikhologa), 4. 31. Leiter B. (2006). The future for philosophy. Clarendon press. 32. McInerney, R.G. (2015). A hermeneutics of love for community-based, participatory action research. Journal of Humanistic Psychology, vol. 53, issue 6, pp. 263-285. 33. Netland J. (2007). Who is My Neighbor?” Reading World Literature through the Hermeneutics of Love. International Journal of Christianity & Education, Volume: 11 issue: 2, pp. 67-82. 34. Nygren, A. (1953). Agape and Eros, Philadelphia, PA: Westminster Press. 35. Packer M.J., Addison R.B. (1989). Entering the Circle: Hermeneutic Investigation in Psychology. SUNY press. 36. Ramberg, B., Gjesdal, K. (2014) "Hermeneutics", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2014 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2014/entries/hermeneutics/ 37. Rennie D. (2007). Methodical hermeneutics and humanistic psychology. The Humanistic Psychologist, Vol 35(1), 1-14. 38. Ricoeur P. (1970/2008). Freud and Philosophy: An Essay on Interpretation. Motilal Banarsidass Publishe. 39. Robbins, B.D. (2015). The heart of humanistic psychology: Human dignity disclosed through a hermeneutics of love. Journal of Humanistic Psychology, vol. 53, issue 6, pp. 223-237. 40. Selig, J.L. (2015). Borne forward ceaselessly into love: A theory of the hermeneutics of love exemplified by Martin Luther King, Jr. Journal of Humanistic Psychology, vol. 53, issue 6, pp.238-262. 41. Shafer I. (1994). From the senses to sense: the hermeneutics of love. Zygon: Journal of Religion and Science, Volume 29, issue 4. 42. Smith J. A. (2004). Reflecting on the development of interpretative phenomenological analysis and its contribution to qualitative research in psychology. Qualitative Research in Psychology, Vol. 1, issue 1. 43. Smith J.A., Flowers P., Larkin M. (2009). Interpretative Phenomenological Analysis: Theory, Method and Research. SAGE. 44. Smith J.A. (2015). Qualitative Psychology: A Practical Guide to Research Methods. SAGE. 45. Soble A. (1990). 1990, The Structure of Love, New Haven: Yale University Press 46. Steele, R. S. (1979). Psychoanalysis and hermeneutics. International Review of Psycho-Analysis, 6(4), 389-411. 47. Strowick, E. (2005). Comparative Epistemology of Suspicion: Psychoanalysis, Literature, and the Human Sciences. Science in Context, 18(4), 649-669. doi:10.1017/S0269889705000700 48. Tervee S.J.S. (2012). Hermeneutics in Psychology and Psychoanalysis. Springer science and business media. 49. Vorobyeva L.I. (2013). How hermeneutics phenomenology can be useful for psychotherapy. Journal for Practicing Psychologist – Russia, vol. 4, pp. 31-55. 50. Wilberg P. (2003). Heidegger, Medicine And 'Scientific Method': The Unheeded Message Of The Zollikon Seminars. New Gnosis Publications. 51. Williams R., Gantt E. (2013). Psychology and the death of aspiration. Theory and Psychology, Volume: 23 issue: 2. 52. Winston B. (2018). The Virtues from the Beatitudes. In: Biblical Principles of Hiring and Developing Employees. Christian Faith Perspectives in Leadership and Business. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. 53. Woo, B. Hoon (2013). "Augustine’s Hermeneutics and Homiletics in De doctrina christianae". Journal of Christian Philosophy 17: 97–117. |